Of
the two science fiction novels we have read so far in this class, the
definition of what it means to be human has been a central theme of both. In Frankenstein,
our reflections on whether the monster was human helped to solidify our
definition of humanity. Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? does
the opposite; every turn in the novel only makes it harder and harder to tell
the difference between humans and androids.
This does not imply that defining our existence is unimportant, quite
the contrary, in fact. By blurring the
line between humans and artificial humans, Philip K. Dick is forcing us to
continually reconsider our definition of humanity. This in turn stresses the importance of the
subject, as well as the natural impossibility of creating a clear definition. The centrality of this idea throughout the
novel lends weight to Brian Aldiss’ definition of science fiction as the
struggle to define our own existence.
This
struggle is clearly represented in the opening chapters of Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? In fact, the first thing Rick Deckard needs
to do when he gets to work is to go check out the Rosen Association’s new
Nexus-6 android to make sure the Voight-Kampff test is still viable. Given Rachael Rosen’s score on the test we
think that it is not, until we discover that she is, in fact, an android. “Does she know?” asks Deckard. “No.
We programmed her completely,” responds Eldon Rosen. (59)
He goes on to admit that the owl is artificial as well, “There are no
owls,” he says. This interaction sets
the tone for the rest of the novel. Of
the four original beings involved in this interaction at the Rosen Association
(Deckard, the two Rosens, and the owl), half of them proved to be
artificial. As far as we know, at least. At this point we can make no assumptions
about anybody’s humanity. Was Eldon an
android as well? Is Deckard? We don’t have sufficient information to make
any proper conclusions. This chapter is
the first of many places in which we will be confused about who is human. It is also the first instance where we must
consider whether it matters. As Deckard
is leaving he says to Rachael, “I’m not going to retire you, Miss Rosen. Good day.”
Knowing that she is an android doesn’t seem to affect the way he interacts
with her. He assures her that she is
safe, politely refers to her as Miss Rosen, and wishes her a good day. Even though she is artificial she is still
conscious, and as such is treated with a certain level of respect, even from
Deckard, a man whose job it is to kill androids.
The
line only becomes blurrier as the novel continues. Deckard’s struggle with the death of Luba
Luft is testament to this. After Resch
kills her Deckard says, “She was a wonderful singer. The planet could have used her. This is insane.” (136) This problem is only exacerbated by the
revelation that Phil Resch is, in fact, human.
Throughout this ordeal Deckard expressed his dislike of Resch and his
style of operation, owing his violence to the fact that he was an android. So here we have an android who, apart from
escaping slavery, is non-violent and a benefit to society. In contrast we have a human who is extremely
violent, to the point where he enjoys killing androids. Philip Dick says it better than I can: “So
much for the distinction between authentic living humans and humanoid
constructs. In that elevator at the
museum, [Deckard] said to himself, I rode down with two creatures, one human,
the other android… and my feelings were the reverse of those intended. Of those I’m accustomed to feel – am required to feel.” (142) We can sympathize with Deckard’s confusion
here. After all, why did Luba have to
die? She contributes beautiful music to
the world. And why does Phil Resch
deserve life? All he brings to this
world is death. Resch argues that Luba
killed humans to escape, that she is a murderer. But can we really fault her for that? Faced with a life of slavery and
discrimination would Resch not have done the same? Would you not have done the same? I certainly would have.
At
this point, Deckard seems to be struggling with emotions he has never felt
before, or at the very least, has never been able to recognize. Throughout his life he’s undoubtedly killed
dozens of androids, and his newly found emotional connection to them is taking
its toll. “I've begun to empathize with androids,
and look what that means. You said it this morning yourself. 'Those poor
andys.' So you know what I'm talking about. That's why I bought the goat. I
never felt like that before,” he said to Iran. (Chapter 15) Like Dick, he has begun to question
everything, and like Dick, he sought an escape from his confusion. It seems he’d hoped the goat would help him
recover his original mindset, which he needs in order to kill the three
remaining androids, which, in turn, he needs to do in order to pay off his new
goat. It’s a vicious cycle, and there are
only two ways he can see to break it.
Option A is
revert. Keep the goat, kill the
androids, and don’t worry about their emotions, or your own. Ignorance is bliss. Harry Bryant seems to see this as the most
sensible option, and is able to convince, or more accurately, command, Deckard
to move forward, despite his misgivings.
Option B is stop. Forget the
androids, forget bounty hunting, and leave before he loses his life or his
mind. It seems that, at this point,
Deckard prefers this solution. Iran and
Bryant disagree, and in their own ways try to convince him to take Option A, but
Deckard will have none of it. He cannot
be swayed to take Option A; it’s too late, he’s already changed. There is only one man, if he can still be
called a man, who can help Deckard now: Mercer.
As soon as Deckard connects to the empathy box, Mercer knows what needs to
be done. Deckard begins to ask him
questions, and Mercer responds with more wisdom than Deckard can even
recognize. Eventually he comes to the
root of the problem: “You will be required to do wrong no matter where you go.
It is the basic condition of life, to be required to violate your own identity.” It is here that Mercer presents a third option,
which Deckard will eventually take. Option
C is to change; grow. However, Deckard
does not see it. “That's all you can
tell me?” says Rick. Mercer’s silence
says it all: “That’s all you need to know.”
And so Deckard
continues, still confused, still obligated to kill three more androids, still
unable to do so. His interaction with
Rachael certainly made it harder, but ultimately I believe it helped him. Before he could come to terms with his own
life, Deckard needed to realize two things.
First, that his feelings for Rachael, and by extension all androids, are
genuine and natural. This is
accomplished by his little affair with her.
As they are leaving the hotel, Rachael brings up that she isn’t alive
and Deckard responds with, "Legally you're not. But really you are.
Biologically. You're not made out of transistorized circuits like a false
animal; you're an organic entity."
If she had kept her mouth shut this would have been the end for Deckard,
but instead she revealed her true motives.
She just had to show him how clever she was, how clever androids
were. It’s ironic really. One brief moment of arrogance, one
exceptionally human mistake unravels her entire scheme and provides Deckard
with his second necessary revelation. Namely,
that there are both similarities and, most importantly, differences between androids
and humans, as there are similarities and differences between any two humans. In broader terms: nothing is black and white,
only shades of grey. Her quick
acceptance of death reminded him of the differences. “… the life force oozed out of her, as he had
so often witnessed before with other androids. The classic resignation.
Mechanical, intellectual acceptance of that which a genuine organism — with two
billion years of the pressure to live and evolve hagriding it — could never
have reconciled itself to.” He may not
have seen it, but she left him with a strong reminder of their similarities as
well: “Thanks for not killing me.” A
remarkably human thing to say, don’t you think?
By the end of the
story Deckard realizes what has happened to him. He has changed; he has successfully chosen
Option C. “I wish I could do to you
[Rachael] what you did to me, he wished. But it can't be done to an android
because they don't care. If I had killed you last night my goat would be alive
now. There's where I made the wrong decision. Yes, he thought; it can all be traced
back to that and to my going to bed with you. Anyhow you were correct about one
thing; it did change me. But not in the way you predicted.” (Chapter 21) And in what way did he actually change? All of his certainties became doubts. All of his answers became questions. He made it through an emotional gauntlet, and
came out stronger on the other side. It
may seem like he knows less than he did at the beginning of the novel, but that
is not the way Deckard, or Dick for that matter, see it. Can we really know anything? Is certainty anything more than an
illusion? Is the knowledge that there
are unanswered questions not more important than the answer to those questions,
or the comfortable delusion that we possess the answer to these questions?
These
questions are the point of this novel.
Is there a distinction between humans and androids? Should there be a distinction? They are certainly alive, and they are
certainly conscious to the same degree we are, so why treat them as inferior? Why treat them as if they aren’t alive? Does their lack of empathy make them
inferior? Many humans are unable to feel
empathy; they are not considered inferior. By the same logic, shouldn’t they be
considered inferior as well? Philip Dick
raises so many questions in this vein and gives us no answers. This is the reason that Dick’s musings fit
well within Aldiss’ definition of science fiction. “Science fiction is the search for a definition of mankind and his status in the universe
which will stand in our advanced but confused state of knowledge,” says Aldiss. Only Philip K. Dick could have, and did, say
it better. Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep? is the epitome of this
statement. In this novel, Dick is
continually searching for a clear definition of mankind, but is never able to
find one. As such, creating a clear
definition of humanity is inherently unimportant, because it is we can’t do it. The importance lies in the search, which
Aldiss explicitly states and Dick implies.
Neither Aldiss nor Dick ever mentions finding a clear definition of
humanity; they recognize that it is impossible.
This may seem confusing, but that is the point. We are confused. There are so many shades of grey between
being human and non-human that we will never be able to find a concise
distinction. But that doesn’t mean we
shouldn’t try. On the contrary, that is
precisely why we should.
1 comment:
Late essays get abbreviated comments.
I like your turn to the "search" for a definition, rather than merely a definition. A like the A/B/C division. The introduction could have been stronger and briefer. Your reading of Rachel is insightful, and maybe my favorite thing about the essay. You included no research (a requirement!).
My biggest question is whether you buy into Deckard's growth. Is he growing into a more advanced, more spiritual being? Or is he the victim of what is basically a con? In other words, we don't need to accept that C is legitimate; even if we do think it's legitimate, we don't need to accept that he's going about it the right way. If you revised again the main thing I'd want (other than a research component) is a sophisticated reading of his ostensible change/progress.
Post a Comment